Understanding the Magna Moralia: Associate Professor George Karamanolis and Dr Solmeng Hirschi
The Magna Moralia is one of the three ethical works attributed to Aristotle in antiquity, next to the Eudemian Ethics and the Nicomachean Ethics. However, the Magna Moralia has not been studied as extensively as the other two treatises, with research focusing largely on the question of authorship and much less on the ethical theory. The team at the University of Vienna aims to establish a new critical edition of the Magna Moralia, to offer a fresh English translation, and to prepare a philosophical commentary. The project will enable a future re-appreciation of the Magna Moralia while contributing to a better understanding of the development of Aristotelian ethics.
What is Magna Moralia and Who Wrote It?
The so-called Magna Moralia (Ἠθικὰ Μεγάλα, MM), together with the Nicomachean Ethics (NE) and the Eudemian Ethics (EE), are the three main ethical works transmitted under the name of Aristotle (a fourth one On Virtues and Vices has always been considered spurious). The MM has received far less scholarly attention than the other two ethical works, mainly because of its disputed authenticity. It is one of the few classical works of ancient Greek philosophy for which we have no reliable edition of the text.
Much is unclear about this work. Firstly, it is unclear what the term ‘Magna’ (Μεγάλα), i.e., ‘great’, signifies in the title of the work. Scholars have suggested that this may describe the size of the individual books of the MM, arguing that the work must have occupied two unusually large papyrus rolls. Others have argued instead that this is because the work is a long summary of the Nicomachean Ethics. Secondly and relatedly, the authorship is unclear. Despite the fact that the entire ancient and medieval tradition perceives the MM as genuinely Aristotle’s, the authorship has been disputed in modern times – at times leading to a virtual consensus against it.
The problem, in a nutshell, is that the style of the work does not look Aristotelian, while the content is close to Aristotle’s ethics, especially the Eudemian Ethics. Most scholars accept that a later editor tampered with the work, but they disagree as to whether the ethical doctrine is Aristotle’s, and if it is, where the work stands from the point of view of the development of Aristotle’s ethics, whether it is the earliest, the latest, or somewhere in the middle. Only a careful scrutiny of the work can help us answer those questions. Our inclination for the time being is that it is a later work written by a Peripatetic student of Aristotle.
Why Is This Treatise on Ethics so Important?
Several aspects of the MM make it distinct from the other ethical works of Aristotle. First, the MM discusses the question of what we should do in case two virtues dictate opposing actions on a given occasion – a situation which never occurs as such in the EE or the NE. The question is specified with regard to bravery and justice (MM 1199b36-1200a11). The MM asks first how it can be the case that one virtue opposes another and then goes on to argue that a perfect virtue is actually informed by practical wisdom, phronêsis, which ultimately decides about the right action. We do not find such a position regarding the role of phronêsis in the NE, although both works describe phronêsis in comparable ways (MM 1198a10-22, NE 1144b28-37).
Another question that does not occur in the other two ethical works of Aristotle is whether the virtues resemble other good things, such as the goods of the body or property (MM 1200a12-14). The MM claims that virtue is unlike other goods in the sense that the increase of virtue will always make us better, while it implies this is not the case with bodily goods or property. The unconditional goodness of virtue, as opposed to the conditional goodness of other things, is a view we find in Plato (e.g., Euthydemus 278-281, Lysis 216d), taken later to extremes by the Stoics. In doing so, the MM offers a hierarchy of goods not found in the other two ethical works of Aristotle. Because the MM takes a view on virtue close to that in the Euthydemus, according to which virtue enables us to make the right use of everything else – in other words, only virtue renders other things good. The treatise is thus crucial because it considerably enriches our knowledge of Aristotle’s ethics or, at the very least, of the ancient reception of Aristotelian ethics.
What Is Virtue as Discussed in Magna Moralia?
The nature of virtue is a central topic in the MM, as in all Aristotelian ethics. Yet we can find some interesting differences between the EE and the NE, as mentioned above. The question, then, is which direction the MM inclines to. While in the EE, virtues of character are states or dispositions of the non-rational part of the soul, which is shaped and guided by the rational one, in the NE, virtues of character are dispositions of the rational part of the soul. They thus mainly affect the way we decide, not the way we act. They are ‘prohairetic states’, i.e., states of prohairesis or choice. In the MM, by contrast, virtues are not such states – at all. According to the MM, we acquire virtues through training and habituation, as with athletics. What is more, they are said to involve pleasure! At the basis of virtue in the MM are thus affections and irrational impulses developed and guided by reason (in this sense, the MM is closer to the EE). In the MM, virtue make someone act correctly; in the NE, virtue makes someone decide correctly.
What Stands out in Magna Moralia as Particularly Meaningful?
The question can be answered in two ways. The MM is traditionally contrasted with the two other treatises of Aristotle’s ethical triad (i.e., the NE and the EE). Hence, one may first want to look for distinctive elements, considering that these are what make the MM meaningful by comparison. The function of phronêsis in helping one make a decision when two virtues conflict (say, as we saw above, bravery and justice) is particularly striking, and so is the emphasis on the role of luck in happiness. What one may subsequently want to make of such differences is another issue. Suffice it to say here that it brings a further set of questions which have a bearing on what we could call the developmentalist and unitarian readings of Aristotle’s writings, in case those differences are taken to be indicative of a lack of authenticity.
However, it is equally interesting to look at the MM and analyse its structure, topics, and style in isolation. From this second perspective, the MM offers a remarkably pragmatic and interlocutory approach to ethical problems. The second-person is used, practical scenarios are given, and some sentences even seem to suggest a deliberate effort to facilitate memorisation, e.g., with stylised catchphrases such as ‘οὐθὲν γὰρ τῶν ὄντων φύσει ἔθει ἄλλως γίνεται’ (I.6 1186a4–5) which one could translate as follows: ‘None of what is by nature can be changed by custom’.
What Are the Implications of Magna Moralia for the Current Day?
The Magna Moralia represents the perfect playground to test several hypotheses – or indeed hidden assumptions – concerning ancient authorship in the early Lyceum, knowledge production and dissemination in the Hellenistic age, or authenticity debates up to this day. This can have serious consequences on text critical and editorial decisions. For instance, should we accept a passage favouring an understanding of the MM as anti-Stoic and thus relatively ‘late’, or should we rather take such a passage to be a subsequent gloss added to an earlier, ‘authentic’ original?
Even trivial questions such as orthographical conventions end up being affected by, and indicative of, such assumptions. To put it differently, precisely because of the problematic tension the MM puts on our expectations concerning Aristotle’s (or a later Peripatetic’s) overall consistency, the quality of the argumentation, and the homogeneity of the style. This treatise makes us confront some of our most fragile and yet momentous assumptions like no other text of the Aristotelian corpus could. Editing the MM today amounts to a complete reappraisal of Aristotle’s ethics qua doctrine, corpus, and edited output.
What Should the Study of Magna Moralia Now Focus On?
There are three foci that require the immediate attention of the scholarly community interested in the MM.
Our first focus must be on the collation of the main witnesses in order to improve on the outdated edition of the Greek text by Franz Susemihl, who knew of about a quarter of all the extant manuscripts and used only a handful of them properly. The point has been highlighted several times since Susemihl, and invaluable preliminary work has already been done. This must now be brought to completion and used to constitute a state-of-the-art text, together with a new translation and commentary.
Our second focus must be on the reassessment of the authenticity of the MM rather than, or at least in addition to, their authorship. Having or not an individual author sanctioning the text we have reconstructed, should not take up all the debate. There is actually little left to be gained in this field and it is much more fertile to shift the focus from a putative authorial intention to the relevance of the text through time. Ancient texts, especially before canonisation took place, were more fluid in their use and transmission than we are used to nowadays (not to mention the absence of copyright).
Our third focus is related to the second one. We must also focus on the knowledge and transmission of the MM in the Byzantine, Latin, and Arabic world. Their history, or rather histories, are still very sketchy. The reception of the MM is complex and not that of a blockbuster. The MM has never represented the first port-of-call for Aristotelian ethics, and whenever people felt attracted to that (instead of, say, the NE), there were specific reasons for it. Our team will endeavour to trace them back and thus contribute to the intellectual history of the Mediterranean.
SHARE
DOWNLOAD E-BOOK
REFERENCE
https://doi.org/10.33548/SCIENTIA1241
MEET THE RESEARCHERS
Associate Professor George Karamanolis
Department of Philosophy, University of Vienna, Vienna, Austria
Dr George Karamanolis was awarded a doctorate in philosophy (DPhil) from Oxford University (UK) in 2001. Following this, he undertook academic and research roles at various universities, including Princeton University (USA), Humboldt University of Berlin (Germany), the Ludwig Maximilian University of Munich (Germany), and the University of Crete (Greece). He is now Associate Professor in Ancient Philosophy at the University of Vienna. His overarching interest is ancient philosophy and, in particular, the study of ancient Platonism, ancient ethics, and logic.
CONTACT
E: magnamoralia.philosophy@univie.ac.at
W: https://ufind.univie.ac.at/en/person.html?id=55005
Dr Solmeng-Jonas Hirschi
Department of Philosophy, University of Vienna, Vienna, Austria
After his undergraduate studies in Berne (CH), Dr Solmeng-Jonas Hirschi was awarded a doctorate in Classics (DPhil) from Oxford University (UK) in 2021. He then moved to Fribourg (Switzerland), where he worked on papyri, and to Rome (Italy) and Berlin (Germany) to work on the Epicurean doctrines concerned with time and astronomy. He is now a postdoctoral research fellow in ancient philosophy at the University of Vienna. In addition to Aristotelian and Epicurean philosophy, he nurtures a keen interest in papyrology, textual criticism, and the role of antiquity in modern and contemporary society.
KEY COLLABORATOR
Mr Till Jesinghaus, University of Vienna, Austria
FUNDING
FWF, Österreichischer Wissenschaftsfonds
Grant-DOI 10.55776/P36936
FURTHER READING
C Brockmann, Zur Überlieferung der aristotelischen Magna Moralia, in F Berger, et al. (eds), Symbolae Berolinenses für Dieter Harlfinger, 1993, Amsterdam, 43–80.
J Cooper, The Magna Moralia and Aristotle’s Moral Philosophy, American Journal of Philology, 1973, 94, 327–349. (Reprinted in his Reason and Emotion, Princeton, 1999, 195–211). DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/293613
M Papathomopoulos, Pour une nouvelle édition des Magna Moralia d’Aristote, Pallas, 2009, 81, 203-207. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/pallas.6872
REPUBLISH OUR ARTICLES
We encourage all formats of sharing and republishing of our articles. Whether you want to host on your website, publication or blog, we welcome this. Find out more
Creative Commons Licence (CC BY 4.0)
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
What does this mean?
Share: You can copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format
Adapt: You can change, and build upon the material for any purpose, even commercially.
Credit: You must give appropriate credit, provide a link to the license, and indicate if changes were made.
SUBSCRIBE NOW
Follow Us
MORE ARTICLES YOU MAY LIKE
Professor Robert B Heimann | Culinary Craftmanship: The Evolution of Pottery for Cooking
Cooking food is arguably one of the most important transitions in human evolution, and initiated hundreds of thousands of years of refinement in both technique and technology. Professor Emeritus Robert B Heimann of TU Bergakademie Freiberg, Germany, recently reviewed the evidence for early cooking vessels and tracks the evolution of their production, identifying important strategies of optimisation using various natural materials, firing methods, and designs to improve durability, functionality, and efficiency over time.
Dr Loren Babcock | Untangling the History of Jefferson’s Giant Ground Sloth
In the spring of 1796, workers mining saltpetre in a western Virginia cave unearthed several unusual bones. This would launch the scientific study of extinct animals in North America and connect one of America’s founding fathers to the early development of palaeontology. Some of these mysterious bones eventually made their way to future US President Thomas Jefferson at his Monticello estate. Dr Loren Babcock from The Ohio State University’s School of Earth Sciences has conducted an extensive review of the complex naming history of this iconic extinct animal. His research untangles over 200 years of inconsistent scientific terminology and establishes the definitive nomenclatural history of what would become known as Megalonyx jeffersonii.
Professor Mark Pagel | Evolution’s Gradual Path: New Model Reveals How Mammals Changed Over Time
A groundbreaking statistical model developed by Professor Mark Pagel and colleagues at the University of Reading demonstrates that even dramatic evolutionary changes in mammals can be explained through gradual Darwinian processes, resolving a long-standing puzzle in evolutionary biology and challenging our understanding of how species change over time.
Professor Layla Branicki | Building Better Workplaces for Neurodivergent Employees
The landscape of work is undergoing a radical transformation, with flexible arrangements and remote working becoming increasingly embedded in organisational culture. However, for the estimated 15-20% of people who are neurodivergent – including those with Autism Spectrum Disorder (ASD), Attention-Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder (ADHD), dyslexia, and other cognitive differences – navigating the workplace can present unique and sometimes overwhelming challenges. Researchers at the University of Bath have conducted the largest UK study of its kind, exploring how flexible working practices can support neurodivergent employees in the workplace, revealing both challenges and opportunities for creating more inclusive work environments.