Dr Mark Sainsbury | Did David Hume Anticipate Daniel Kahneman’s View of the Mind?

Nov 22, 2023 | Arts, Humanities & Social Sciences

In his best-selling book Thinking, Fast and Slow (2011), Daniel Kahneman distinguishes between two systems of thought: System 1 involves fast, intuitive thinking, whereas System 2 is characterised as slow, reason-based thinking. More than two hundred years earlier, the philosopher, economist and historian David Hume made what Dr Mark Sainsbury (University of Texas at Austin) argues is a similar distinction. Like Kahneman, Hume proposed that much of our behaviour is determined in the first (fast) way rather than the second (slow) way. For both Hume and Kahneman, the upshot is that Reason plays a much less important role in our lives than is often thought.

Kahneman: Thinking Fast and Slow

Daniel Kahneman is a psychologist and economist, notable for his work on the psychology of judgement and decision-making and in behavioural economics, for which he was awarded a Nobel Memorial Prize in 2002 (which he says he would have shared with his collaborator, Amos Tversky, had Amos not died). His book Thinking, Fast and Slow summarises much of his research and sold more than 10 million copies within a year of publication.

Kahneman’s main claim is that our mind operates in two very different ways. It’s as if it contains two systems, System 1 and System 2. System 1 works automatically, quickly and effortlessly, facilitating routine tasks, and often resulting in thoughts that arise in us involuntarily. The operations of System 2, by contrast, are typically conscious and effortful, and are sometimes needed to correct the products of System 1. When we are driving on familiar roads, not in a hurry, and under normal traffic conditions, System 1 is in charge: We effortlessly negotiate the bends, the turns and the traffic lights without having to attend closely to what we are doing. Things are very different if it is rush hour, we are driving in a foreign city where they drive on the ‘wrong’ side of the road, and we are unsure of our route. Here, System 2 will be active as we focus on the task and struggle with explicit thoughts about what signs to follow, efforts that may make us unable to continue an ordinary conversation.

Kahneman says that System 1 is essential to survival, in other animals as well as humans. Much of his research has been devoted to showing how it can mislead, even in simple situations. A famous example is the bat-and-ball problem: a bat and a ball together cost $1.10, and the bat costs a dollar more than the ball. How much does the ball cost? The easy and automatic System 1 may well make us think the answer is 10 cents. System 2 requires rather more effort to correct this mistake.

Hume Against Reason

David Hume is best known as a philosopher, though he also wrote a substantial History of England, and contributed to the political and economic debates of his day. In his first major philosophical work, the Treatise on Human Nature, he made two attacks on the preeminence of Reason. One relates to action, concerning which he argued that ‘Reason is, and ought only to be, the slave of the passions’. This was a revolutionary thought in an era when Reason was frequently extolled as the source of all morality and religion.

The other attack on Reason, and the one in which his position closely resembles Kahneman’s, relates to beliefs about states of affairs we have not experienced, for example, what the future holds. Whereas it was customary in his era to try to account for these beliefs as based on Reason, Hume argued that this was impossible: Reason discovers what is logically necessary, whereas there is no logically necessary relation between the past and the future. Instead, he claims that our expectations about the future are produced by what he refers to as Custom or habit: the habitual projection of observed regularities. It is Custom or habit, not Reason, that makes us expect the patterns we have already encountered to continue.

Accordingly, for Hume, Reason plays a much smaller part in our lives than often supposed. Many cognitive activities often attributed to Reason need to be explained in terms of Custom and habit.

Hume’s Prescience

Both Hume and Kahneman sought to explain how the mind processes information and how this affects action. Both identified two systems: Kahneman’s System 1 is similar to Hume’s Custom or habit, and his System 2 is similar to Hume’s Reason. Like Kahneman’s System 1, Hume’s Custom is fast, effortless, and operates independently of conscious control. Like Kahneman’s System 2, Hume’s Reason is typically under voluntary control but is slow and ‘laboured’.

Both Hume and Kahneman further propose that the more automatic, faster system is available to animals and to very young humans. Hume reminds us that birds engage in complex tasks like nest-building and raising chicks. We attribute this to instinct, and we should recognise that, in Hume’s words, Custom, too, is ‘a species of instinct or mechanical power’.

Hume did not denigrate Custom, nor does Kahneman denigrate System 1. For Hume, Custom is ‘the great guide of life’ and thus utterly essential to our survival and well-being. For Kahneman, System 1 is ‘the origin of most of what we do right’. Hume believed that Reason, by contrast, is an uncertain and untrustworthy guide, and Kahneman stresses how we can be misled by System 2.

Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature is not only an important and pioneering philosophical work but also a contribution to psychology, anticipating recent work like Kahneman’s. He did indeed achieve the goal he stated in the subheading to his Treatise: ‘an attempt to introduce the experimental method of reasoning into moral subjects’. His conception of the ‘experimental method’ was very different from the modern conception: Hume relied largely on careful introspective reflection on his own mental activities. But he reached conclusions remarkably similar to those that, under the influence of scientists like Kahneman, are beginning to become standard today.

Forming a Better Understanding

Written some 250 years ago in the language of its day, Hume’s text requires careful exegesis, especially as his use of language is not always consistent. These are obstacles to establishing the thesis that Hume anticipated Kahneman. Dr Mark Sainsbury of the University of Texas at Austin has worked to overcome these obstacles by paying careful attention to the texts. For example, Hume uses the crucial word ‘Reason’ for different things, without warning, including ‘demonstrative’ reasoning (purely logical), ‘probable reasoning’, ‘moral reasoning’ and ‘experimental reasoning’. These last three are all species of reasoning, in that they rely on explicit premises and conclusions, but they are not intended as demonstrative, only ‘probable’, as when one infers, from the premise that since one has heard church bells every Sunday one has lived here, that one will hear bells today also. If one considers the premise one might reason to the conclusion, or one might notice that an important premise is missing (that today is Sunday). Sometimes, however, one just forms an expectation with no explicit rehearsal of any premises, just by habit. In that case, Custom, not Reason, is at work.

Appreciating Humes Contribution

Kahneman’s view of the mind was substantiated by a large number of very clever and telling experiments using human subjects. Hume speaks of the ‘experimental method’, but conforming to the standard practice of his time, he conducted no such experiments. Nonetheless, their overall pictures of the nature of the mind are remarkably similar, justifying Sainsbury’s claim that Hume ‘…was hundreds of years ahead of his time’.

SHARE

DOWNLOAD E-BOOK

REFERENCE

https://doi.org/10.33548/SCIENTIA954

MEET THE RESEARCHER


Dr Mark Sainsbury

Department of Philosophy
University of Texas at Austin
Austin, TX
USA

Dr Mark Sainsbury is Jesse H. Jones Regents Professor in Liberal Arts at the University of Texas at Austin (USA), and was formerly the Susan Stebbing Professor of Philosophy at King’s College London (UK). He received a BA in Philosophy, Politics and Economics, and an MA in Philosophy, both from the University of Oxford (UK), before completing his doctorate (DPhil) at the same institution. His current research examines problems in the logic and metaphysics of intentionality, and he is renowned for his work on philosophical logic, the philosophy of language, and the philosophies of Bertrand Russell and Gottlob Frege. He was the Editor of the leading philosophy journal Mind from 1990 to 2000, and is the author of eight books. His fascinating and influential work in philosophy has led to his election as a Fellow of the British Academy and an Honorary Fellow of Corpus Christi College at the University of Oxford.

CONTACT

E: marksainsbury@austin.utexas.edu

W: https://www.marksainsbury.net/

FURTHER READING

Mark Sainsbury, Hume and Kahnemans dual systems, 2023. https://www.marksainsbury.net/uploads/9/7/2/9/97295048/h_and_k.pdf

Mark Sainsbury, Meeting the Hare in her doubles: Causal belief and general belief. In Marina Frasca-Spada and P. J. E. Kail (Eds.), Impressions of Hume, 2005. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199256525.001.0001

More than 50 of Dr Sainsbury’s papers can be downloaded from https://www.marksainsbury.net/

REPUBLISH OUR ARTICLES

We encourage all formats of sharing and republishing of our articles. Whether you want to host on your website, publication or blog, we welcome this. Find out more

Creative Commons Licence (CC BY 4.0)

This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. Creative Commons License

What does this mean?

Share: You can copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format

Adapt: You can change, and build upon the material for any purpose, even commercially.

Credit: You must give appropriate credit, provide a link to the license, and indicate if changes were made.

SUBSCRIBE NOW


Follow Us

MORE ARTICLES YOU MAY LIKE

El Dr. Jean Muteba Rahier | Promoviendo los derechos humanos de Afrodescendientes en Latinoamérica

El Dr. Jean Muteba Rahier | Promoviendo los derechos humanos de Afrodescendientes en Latinoamérica

El Dr. Jean Muteba Rahier es un destacado académico, profesor y defensor de los derechos humanos, actualmente afiliado al Departamento de Estudios Globales y Socioculturales de la Universidad Internacional de Florida (FIU). Sus iniciativas, contribuciones académicas y sus proyectos de investigación exploran la aplicación de ‘leyes étnico-raciales’ en la práctica de los sistemas judiciales latinoamericanos para la defensa de los derechos humanos de los afrodescendientes. El Dr. Rahier explica cómo esta indagación amplía los horizontes académicos y busca contribuir a la generación de un conocimiento esencial para contrarrestar y remediar tanto las manifestaciones solapadas y casi imperceptibles del racismo anti-negro en la región, así como sus manifestaciones escandalosamente más visibles.

Annual Review of Applied Linguistics | Working Towards Social Justice in Applied Linguistics Research

Annual Review of Applied Linguistics | Working Towards Social Justice in Applied Linguistics Research

The Annual Review of Applied Linguistics recently published an issue dedicated to research by emerging scholars working at the cutting edge of social justice in applied linguistics. Together, the members of the journal’s editorial board developed an exciting new model that would enable the journal to act upon calls in the field to question existing review systems in academic publishing. To this end, the board devised a novel collaborative, iterative review process and actively recruited early-career and emergent minoritised scholars to publish in the issue.

Dr Jean Muteba Rahier | Championing Human Rights for Afrodescendants in Latin America

Dr Jean Muteba Rahier | Championing Human Rights for Afrodescendants in Latin America

Dr Jean Muteba Rahier is a distinguished scholar, professor, and human rights advocate. Currently based in the Department of Global & Sociocultural Studies at Florida International University, Dr Rahier’s initiatives, scholarly contributions, and ongoing research projects explore the processes of adoption and application of ‘ethnoracial law’ in the practice of Latin American judicial systems for the defence of Afrodescendants’ human rights. He explains here how this exploration broadens academic horizons and seeks to contribute to the knowledge production necessary to oppose and remedy both the small, almost imperceptible, and the scandalously visible acts of ordinary anti-Black racism in the region.